Space seems like an empty box that lives
through time. This can already be classified as a “better model”, as you can
see in the table below. However, this tacitly held model makes people wonder:
If I toss a coin and find myself with the result being “tails”, where is the other me, the one who
found “heads”, the other possibility which physics can no longer ignore, and which
good philosophy has always known to be equivalent?

Has a universe popped up
next door to this one?

The question “Where are the other outcome worlds?” is similar to “Where are the other times, for example
tomorrow, where is it?
” The answers are thus similar.

Great philosophers like Kant and Wittgenstein knew half
of the answer implicitly; they understood the ‘apriority’ of space, time, and
causality. Modern physics clarifies it, making it palatable to the common intellectual.
We physicists provided first empirical data that were incompatible with naïve
models, but proof alone does not convince.

More importantly, we provide better visually
intuitive models, such as Minkowski’s space-time diagrams in case of Einstein’s
special relativity, and now the Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen Many-World model in
case of relativistic quantum theory.

So where is tomorrow, where are the
parallel worlds? They are not anywhere.
Or you could as well say that they are right here, because this is the place we
are talking about, namely you near that tossed coin, but at another time,
tomorrow, or being in a slightly different configuration, heads instead of
tails. “When” and “how”, not “where”! However,
we strongly desire to point to a place inside a space, a model, and we are not
satisfied until we can
– I personally did not rest for many years until I
had a geometrical model of parallel worlds, all the time fully aware of the
fundamental silliness, perhaps impossibility of the endeavor.

Luckily, it
turned out to be possible.

This is what the common box, space-time,
and many-world models are about. They allow our mind to consider the issue in
familiar ways, namely those of a hunter-gatherer with a visual cortex so
impressive that his nose has become obsolete. Humans ‘understand’ such issues
if they can imagine a model with places and paths where they can point their fingers:
Here is the past, and there is the future, and that is a path
of light from here to there, and now you see.”
All of a sudden we have insight; the
difficult has become trivial.

Quantum mechanics is very similar to
relativity theory and even similar to the common box model already in this
sense: The box includes all locations together, relativity theory is about
including also different times properly, and quantum mechanics is about furthermore
including all relevant possibilities, too – these connections are illustrated
in the table below. Our intuition decreases with decreasing accessibility (top yellow
row), so we have to work harder to grasp the model.

 

 

Overview
of models: The blue text is understandable through this article. Orange
background: This decade’s cutting edge, not yet known to mainstream. Red:
Hypothetical, may be wrong! (Original work, please use, but please use with
proper attribution)

If you want to model not only different places
in a three dimensional (3D) space but also different times, you need four
dimensional (4D) structures, which are listed in the third column in the table.
Space at a certain time is then a 3D “cut” through that 4D structure, a cross
section. This is *not* yet Einstein relativity
theory!

We are now inside the second row of the table; the better models
are in the row below. Einstein’s special relativity is: observers who move
relative to each other disagree on the orientation of the cut: If I move
relative to you, my 3D “box-right-now” has only a 2D slice in common with your
box-right-now; all my other parallel 2D slices are at different times
relative to you.

Note: this is not just about mere location
and time labels. Measured lengths differ and twins can meet in the future
having aged differently (the twin paradox).

Something very similar happens in quantum
physics. Not only are different outcomes included (fourth column). That is
true, but naïve many-world models that are confused with the concept of the
multiverse (almost all science writers
etc. confuse this - see here and here for the crucial difference!
) do not have the correct symmetries. Again, the proper ‘Everett relativity’
becomes obvious in better models in the row below.

Locations, times, and now also outcomes
depend on the observer’s situation. Again, this is not merely about different
labels. At a certain angle in the EPR experiment, the Alice
that observes 0 meets a Bob who got 1, while the Alice that got 1 finds a Bob that got 0.

 

Cross
section of an EPR MW model with correct quantum probabilities (the classical-to-quantum transition model is simpler): Every small area is a parallel world of Carl as he
observes the measurement results from Alice and Bob. Source: [1] and more explanation here.

Let us briefly review in order to reveal a
problem: The 3D box is a useful model in everyday life and classical physics. In
physics books, we see 2D pictures of the 3D model. If you want to understand
time, the 3D box is a misleading model. You need 4D Minkowski space-time.
Still, our pictures are mostly 2D. For understanding probability better, 4D
space-time is insufficient. You need something that includes not just different
times, but different possibilities. This is why there are now many-world
models. So far so good, but the problem with them is: They have many more
dimensions. 2D slices like the one above need a lot of explanation.
Nevertheless, there are these comprehensible representations now and there is a
touchable 3D model
possible, too! Finally we have the satisfaction of
understanding like a human must understand:

“Look, there
is Alice
finding tails and there is Bob
finding heads.”
“But where
are Alice and Bob both finding tails for example?”
“Right there
at that angle.”
“Oh, yes, and I see right away that there are so few of those possibilities. Nice,
but wait; do they find the quantum probabilities? Does the model violate the Bell inequality?”
“Well, go ahead and count, there and there ... , you can
put your finger on them and count now. Then rotate the angle further and count
again.”
“ … Oh, wow … but … the model is actually so
simple … ”

A new version of the introduction to the
EPR-MW model
has just today been made available
– it is yet more accessible
to lay persons and has many simple drawings that slowly increase in complexity
until the above 2D picture can be fully understood. Be one of the first people
in the world who already understand this exciting model and its significance for science and philosophy; connect it with your creative work before everybody else
catches up.

---------------------

Remark: Einstein-Everett
relativity is almost unacceptable to our socially evolved belief system,
because it threatens naïve rationalizations of the concept of responsible
agency by further clarifying the illusionary nature of the feeling of “free
will” that coevolved with social systems depending largely on control via
communicated abstract meaning. Therefore, crackpots, religious, etc. attack
demystifications such as attempted here. Comments are tightly monitored in
order to ensure a useful comment section for reasonable readers. Thank you for
your understanding.

Old NID
138014
Categories

Latest reads

Article teaser image
Donald Trump does not have the power to rescind either constitutional amendments or federal laws by mere executive order, no matter how strongly he might wish otherwise. No president of the United…
Article teaser image
The Biden administration recently issued a new report showing causal links between alcohol and cancer, and it's about time. The link has been long-known, but alcohol carcinogenic properties have been…
Article teaser image
In British Iron Age society, land was inherited through the female line and husbands moved to live with the wife’s community. Strong women like Margaret Thatcher resulted.That was inferred due to DNA…